Think about that: Whatever is, is right.
Pope had no idea what he was really advocating. Living in a world that was still dominated by Christian culture, law, morals, etc., for Pope “Nature” and “Right” seemed like good things. Little did he know just how depraved a society built solely on nature could actually be.
Pope died in 1744. A mere four years earlier was born another influential literary figure across the English channel: the Marquis de Sade. Pope would not live to see the French Revolution where they idolized “Nature” and enshrined “lady reason” in the cathedrals. Sade not only lived through it, he provided the most radical and most consistent view of what a system of morals built only on natural impulses would look like. In his rigorous consistency with “Nature,” Sade shows how deluded a dream like Pope’s really is, though Sade embraced it wholeheartedly. He pulls back the curtains on a dark, sadistic (a word derived from his very name), heartless, murderous, pornographic, backstage of evil. His basis for this? The fact that godless Nature dictates a lawless society: “for what should we, who have no religion, do with law?”[1]
He continued, “Nature, equally dictating virtues and vices in us . . . in reason of the need Nature has of the one and the other, what she inspires in us becomes a very reliable gauge by which to adjust exactly what is good and bad.” While this sounds somewhat acceptable—he is still speaking of both good and evil, right?—he had much more in mind. Unlike Pope, Sade would not be hindered by the moral values of good and evil already entrenched around him. He would rigorously seek ought only that which Nature dictated “in us.”
For example, he would advocate abolishing the death penalty, but not because he thought it too harsh a penalty for the crime of murder, but because he did not think murder is a crime to be punished at all. And thus, he argued, we should also abolish all laws against murder. Murder, after all, is a perfectly natural impulse.[2] Society must learn to accept it.
In fact, sometimes mass murder is profitable for society, for example, to keep the population down and thus prevent poverty. For this, Sade prescribed infanticide: “The human species must be purged from the cradle.”[3]
Sade was just warming up. Once denuding society of punishment for the highest offense of murder, the way was clear for his favorite “natural” acts—those of sexual deviance. Sade advocated the forced submission of all women to all men unconditionally, incest, sodomy, pederasty, as well as the eating of feces as a matter of taste and sexual pleasure.[4]
Of course, some atheists today are still brave enough to say as much as that rape is, in fact, “natural.” Sam Harris, for example, has admitted, “There is, after all, nothing more natural than rape.”[5] Although he pleads that it is still not “good.” A few years back a book titled A Natural History of Rape stirred up controversy with the same admission, “We fervently believe that, just as the leopard’s spots and the giraffe’s elongated neck are the results of aeons of past Darwinian selection, so is rape.”[6] Like Sam, the authors were quick to point out, “We’re not saying something is good even if it’s natural.”[7] Nevertheless, the book gives scientific, Darwinian, and academic sanction to the belief, “Rape is natural.”
At such a juncture, it seems that an ethic like Pope’s offers humanity little help: “Whatever is, is right,” entails, “Rape is; therefore, Rape is right.”
But on what basis, then, can a naturalist decry (contra Sade) such an act as evil? Since the atheist/naturalist believes nothing exists except nature, a consistent doctrine of “good” versus “bad” will be impossible to find. What is good for one man may or may not be good for another. One man’s pleasure is simply another woman’s (or little girl’s) pain, and who is to judge between them except for might itself?
This is why atheists like Sade are so important: they expose how more moderate atheists are really arbitrary and soft in both their logic and their practice. Sade shows how cruel and heartless the naturalistic ethic truly is:
With the naturalistic ethic, what is natural is good; and (if God does not exist) there’s no one who has the right to say otherwise. Ergo, rape is not only natural, but Nature herself proves that rape is acceptable by equipping the rapist with greater strength than his victims.
Nor do the age or well-being of the female affect the scenario:
[O]nce you concede me the proprietary right of enjoyment, that right is independent of the effect [harm] it produces. . . . The issue of her well-being . . . is irrelevant. As soon as concern for this consideration threatens to detract from or enfeeble the enjoyment of him who desires her . . . this consideration for age ceases to exist.[10]
In other words, in a naturalistic world, get away with whatever you can get away with. That is, in a nturalistic world, might makes right.
In a Christian world, of course, we have an infinitely better system. Mankind—male and female—are created in God’s image. They are thus designed to express God’s will—the Ten Commandments—in society. An attack on another person bearing God’s image is an attack on God Himself. To debase and dishonor that image through scheming, kidnapping, bondage, sexual violence and theft—i.e., rape—is essentially to break the entire second table of the Law in one act. As such a consummate act of rejection of God and God’s prized image on earth, rape deserves the death penalty.
This morality is transcendent, it descends from above, and lifts man to a higher purpose, honor, and meaning. Naturalistic ethics debases man to the level of lawless, meaningless matter. In such a world, the issue is not whether rape is good or evil, it is who can ultimately get away with raping whom. Reject God, and you destroy law, and open the floodgates to destroy man as well.
Naturalism is, therefore, the rape of morality.
The next great consistent atheist after Sade came a generation later in Friedrich Nietzsche. He used the same rigorous logic as Sade: “When one gives up the Christian faith, one pulls the right to Christian morality out from under one’s feet. . . .” Thus, when naturalists
As long as they continue to do this, we should continue to refute them by referencing the more consistent atheists. The point is not to drive them actually to become more consistent atheists—at least not in practice—but rather drive them to admit where the logic of the naturalist position leads, and hopefully to turn to the only God who can save them from it.
And in the meantime, whether Dostoevsky said it or not, the truth remains, “If God does not exist, all things are permissible.”
For example, he would advocate abolishing the death penalty, but not because he thought it too harsh a penalty for the crime of murder, but because he did not think murder is a crime to be punished at all. And thus, he argued, we should also abolish all laws against murder. Murder, after all, is a perfectly natural impulse.[2] Society must learn to accept it.
In fact, sometimes mass murder is profitable for society, for example, to keep the population down and thus prevent poverty. For this, Sade prescribed infanticide: “The human species must be purged from the cradle.”[3]
Sade was just warming up. Once denuding society of punishment for the highest offense of murder, the way was clear for his favorite “natural” acts—those of sexual deviance. Sade advocated the forced submission of all women to all men unconditionally, incest, sodomy, pederasty, as well as the eating of feces as a matter of taste and sexual pleasure.[4]
Of course, some atheists today are still brave enough to say as much as that rape is, in fact, “natural.” Sam Harris, for example, has admitted, “There is, after all, nothing more natural than rape.”[5] Although he pleads that it is still not “good.” A few years back a book titled A Natural History of Rape stirred up controversy with the same admission, “We fervently believe that, just as the leopard’s spots and the giraffe’s elongated neck are the results of aeons of past Darwinian selection, so is rape.”[6] Like Sam, the authors were quick to point out, “We’re not saying something is good even if it’s natural.”[7] Nevertheless, the book gives scientific, Darwinian, and academic sanction to the belief, “Rape is natural.”
At such a juncture, it seems that an ethic like Pope’s offers humanity little help: “Whatever is, is right,” entails, “Rape is; therefore, Rape is right.”
But on what basis, then, can a naturalist decry (contra Sade) such an act as evil? Since the atheist/naturalist believes nothing exists except nature, a consistent doctrine of “good” versus “bad” will be impossible to find. What is good for one man may or may not be good for another. One man’s pleasure is simply another woman’s (or little girl’s) pain, and who is to judge between them except for might itself?
This is why atheists like Sade are so important: they expose how more moderate atheists are really arbitrary and soft in both their logic and their practice. Sade shows how cruel and heartless the naturalistic ethic truly is:
[W]hat right do you have to assert that women ought to be exempted from the blind submission to men’s caprices Nature dictates?[8]
[W]e have received from Nature the right indiscriminately to express our wishes to all women . . . we have the right to compel their submission . . . Indeed! has Nature not proven that we have that right, by bestowing upon us the strength needed to bend women to our will. . . . I have incontestable rights to the enjoyment of her; I have the right to force from her this enjoyment, if she refuses me it for whatever the cause may be.[9]
With the naturalistic ethic, what is natural is good; and (if God does not exist) there’s no one who has the right to say otherwise. Ergo, rape is not only natural, but Nature herself proves that rape is acceptable by equipping the rapist with greater strength than his victims.
Nor do the age or well-being of the female affect the scenario:
[O]nce you concede me the proprietary right of enjoyment, that right is independent of the effect [harm] it produces. . . . The issue of her well-being . . . is irrelevant. As soon as concern for this consideration threatens to detract from or enfeeble the enjoyment of him who desires her . . . this consideration for age ceases to exist.[10]
“Once you concede me the proprietary right to enjoyment. . . .” Now that is a profound notion of which all naturalists should take note. Taking nature as a source of morals creates a paradox for the naturalist: while he knows he has no authority from Nature to forbid the individual the right to enjoyment, he must do so in order to stop the rapist from pursuing his enjoyment. The Sadean rapist, of course, only cares about his personal enjoyment, and cares nothing about temporarily denying the same for his victim.
But here the naturalist steps into a real catch-22. In wishing to prevent the rapist his enjoyment, the “good” naturalist must rely upon the same ethical standard as the rapist: by saying that it is sometimes acceptable to prevent another person’s enjoyment, the naturalist has adopted Sade’s standard. He is, in principle, no better than Sade. Of course, which one prevails—in a naturalistic world, this is—will depend only on which one is more cunning, secretive, and/or powerful enough to impose their will.In other words, in a naturalistic world, get away with whatever you can get away with. That is, in a nturalistic world, might makes right.
In a Christian world, of course, we have an infinitely better system. Mankind—male and female—are created in God’s image. They are thus designed to express God’s will—the Ten Commandments—in society. An attack on another person bearing God’s image is an attack on God Himself. To debase and dishonor that image through scheming, kidnapping, bondage, sexual violence and theft—i.e., rape—is essentially to break the entire second table of the Law in one act. As such a consummate act of rejection of God and God’s prized image on earth, rape deserves the death penalty.
This morality is transcendent, it descends from above, and lifts man to a higher purpose, honor, and meaning. Naturalistic ethics debases man to the level of lawless, meaningless matter. In such a world, the issue is not whether rape is good or evil, it is who can ultimately get away with raping whom. Reject God, and you destroy law, and open the floodgates to destroy man as well.
Naturalism is, therefore, the rape of morality.
The next great consistent atheist after Sade came a generation later in Friedrich Nietzsche. He used the same rigorous logic as Sade: “When one gives up the Christian faith, one pulls the right to Christian morality out from under one’s feet. . . .” Thus, when naturalists
actually believe that they know “intuitively” what is good and evil, when they therefore suppose that they no longer require Christianity as the guarantee of morality, we merely witness the effects of the dominion of the Christian value judgment and an expression of the strength and depth of this dominion. . . .[11]
This continues today as a perfect description of most of the modern atheists. Logically, they have pulled the foundations of morality out from under their feet. Sade has show us where this logically should lead. But rape and pederasty make for bad PR. Thus, atheists continue to steal necessary bits of Christian morality while denying the Christ who gave it.As long as they continue to do this, we should continue to refute them by referencing the more consistent atheists. The point is not to drive them actually to become more consistent atheists—at least not in practice—but rather drive them to admit where the logic of the naturalist position leads, and hopefully to turn to the only God who can save them from it.
And in the meantime, whether Dostoevsky said it or not, the truth remains, “If God does not exist, all things are permissible.”
Nenhum comentário:
Postar um comentário